\^^^
IN MEMORIAM
FLORIAN CAJORl
i
i^^ CX^-'in^
«^
\s
The School Edition
EUCLID'S
ELEMENTS OF GEOMETRY,
THE FIEST SIX BOOKS,
CHIEFLY FROM THE TEXT OF De. SIMSON,
WITH EXPLANATORY NOTES ;
A SERIES OF QUESTIONS ON EACH BOOK;
AND A SELECTION OF GEOMETRICAL EXERCISES FROM
THE SENATE-HOUSE AND COLLEGE EXAMINATION
PAPERS : WITH HINTS, &c.
DESIGNED FOE THE USE OP THE JTTITIOE CLASSES Ilf PUBI.IC AND
PEIVATB SCHOOLS.
EOBEET POTTS, M.A.,
IBliriTY COLLEGE.
CORRECTED AND IMPROFED.
LONDON:
JOHN W. PARKER, SON, AND BOURN, 445, WEST STRAND.
MNDCCO^LXnJ?
L02f DON :
WILLIAM STEVENS, PHINTER, 37, BELL TAED,
TEMPLE BAR.
PREFACE TO THE THIRD EDITION. ^^ ^ ^
Some time after the publication of an Octavo Edition of'Ettcua's^^**
Elements with Geometrical Exercises, &c., designed for the use of
Academical Students ; at the request of some schoolmasters of emi-
nence, a duodecimo Edition of the Six Books was put forth on the
same plan for the use of Schools. Soon after its appearance, Pro-
fessor Christie, the Secretary of the Royal Society, in the Preface to
his Treatise on Descriptive Geometry for the use of the Royal Military'
Academy, was pleased to notice these works in the following terms :—
" When the greater Portion of this Part of the Course was printed,
and had for some time been in use in the Academy, a new Edition of
Euclid's Elements, by Mr. Robert Potts, M.A., of Trinity College,
Cambridge, which is likely to supersede most others, to the extent, at
least, of the Six Books, was published. From the manner of arrang-
ing the Demonstrations, this edition has the advantages of the
symbolical form, and it is at the same time free from the manifold
objections to which that form is open. The duodecimo edition of this
Work, comprising only the first Six Books of Euclid, with Deductions
from them, having been introduced at this Institution as a text-book,
now renders any other Treatise on Plane Geometry unnecessary in
our course of Mathematics."
For the very favourable reception which both Editions have met
with, the Editor's grateful acknowledgements are due. It has been his
desire in putting forth a revised Edition of the School Euclid, to render
the work in some degree more worthy of the favour which the former
editions have received, tn the present Edition several errors and
oversights have been corrected and some additions made to the notes :
the questions on each book have been considerably augmented and a
better arrangement of the Geometrical Exercises has been attempted :
and lastly, some hints and remarks on them have been given to assist
the learner. The additions made to the present Edition amount to
more than fifty pages, and, it is hoped, that they will render the work
more useful to the learner.
And here an occasion may be taken to quote the opinions of some
able men respecting the use and importance of the Mathematical
Sciences.
On the subject of Education in its most extensive sense, an ancient
writer " directs the aspirant after excellence to commence with the
Science of Moral Culture; to proceed next to Logic ; next to Mathe-
matics ; next to Physics ; and lastly, to Theology." Another writer
on Education would place Mathematics before Logic, which (he
remarks) " seems the preferable course : for by practising itself in the
IV PREFACE.
former, the mind becomes stored with distinctions ; the faculties of
constanc} and firmness are established; and its rule is always to dis-
tinguish between cavilling and investigation— between close reasoning
and cross reasoning ; for the contrary of all which habits, those are for
the most part noted, who apply themselves to Logic without studying
in some department of Mathematics ; taking noise and wrangling for
proficiency, and thinking refutation accomplished by the instancing
of a doubt. This will explain the inscription placed by Plato over the
door of his house : * Whoso knows not Geometry, let him not enter
here.' On the precedence of Moral Culture, however, to all the other
Sciences, the acknowledgement is general, and the agreement entire."
The same writer recommends the study of the Mathematics, for the
cure of "compound ignorance." " Of this," he proceeds to say, " the
essence is opinion not agi'eeable to fact ; and it necessarily involves
another opinion, namely, that we are already possessed of knowledge.
So that besides not knowing, we know not that we know not ; and
hence its designation of compound ignorance. In like manner, as of
many chronic complaints and established maladies, no cure can be
efi*ected by physicians of the body : of this, no cure can be efi'ected by
physicians of the mind : for with a pre-supposal of knowledge in our
own regard, the pursuit and acquirement of further knowledge is not
to be looked for. The approximate cure, and one from which in the
main much benefit may be anticipated, is to engage the patient in the
study of measures (Geometry, computation, &c.); for in such pursuits
the true and the false are separated by the clearest interval, and no
room is left for the intrusions of fancy. From these the mind may
discover the delight of certainty; and when, on returning to his own
opinions, it finds in them no such sort of repose and gratification, it
may discover their erroneous character, its ignorance may become
simple, and a capacity for the acquirement of truth and virtue be
obtained."
Lord Bacon, the founder of Inductive Philosophy, was not insen-
sible of the high importance of the Mathematical Sciences, as appears
in the following passage from his work on " The Advancement of
Learning."
" The Mathematics are either pure or mixed. To the pure Mathe-
matics are those sciences belonging which handle quantity determinate,
merely severed from any axioms of natural philosophy; and these are
two. Geometry, and Arithmetic; the one handling quantity continued,
and the other dissevered. Mixed hath for subject some axioms or
parts of natural philosophy, and considereth quantity determined, as it
is auxiliary and incident unto them. For many parts of nature can
PBEFACE. V
neither be invented with sufficient subtlety, nor demonstrated with
sufficient perspicuity, nor accommodated unto use with sufficient
dexterity, without the aid and intervening of the Mathematics : of
which sort are perspective, music, astronomy, cosmography, archi-
tecture, enginery, and divers others.
" In the Mathematics I can report no deficience, except it be that
men do not sufficiently understand the excellent use of the pure
Mathematics, in that they do remedy and cure many defects in the
wit and faculties intellectual. For, if the wit be dull, they sharpen it ;
if too wandering, they fix it ; if too inherent in the sense, they abstract
it. So that as tennis is a game of no use in itself, but of great use in
respect that it maketh a quick eye, and a body ready to put itself into
all postures ; so in the Mathematics, that use which is collateral and
intervenient, is no less worthy than that which is principal and
intended. And as for the mixed Mathematics, I may only make this I
prediction, that there cannot fail to be more kinds of them, as nature |
grows further disclosed." I
How truly has this prediction been fulfilled in the subsequent
advancement of the Mixed Sciences, and in the applications of the
pure Mathematics to Natural Philosophy!
Dr. Whewell, in his " Thoughts on the Study of Mathematics,"
has maintained, that mathematical studies judiciously pursued, form
one of the most efi'ective means of developing and cultivating the
reason : and that "the object of a liberal education is to develope the
whole mental system of man; — to make his speculative inferences
coincide with his practical convictions ; — to enable him to render a
reason for the belief that is in him, and not to leave him in the con-
dition of Solomon's sluggard, who is wiser in his own conceit than
seven men that can render a reason." And in his more recent work
entitled, " Of a Liberal Education, &c." he has more fully shewn the
importance of Geometry as one of the most effectual instruments
of intellectual education. In page 55 he thus proceeds: — "But
besides the value of Mathematical Studies in Education, as a perfect
example and complete exercise of demonstrative reasoning; Mathe-
matical Truths have this additional recommendation, that they have
always been referred to, by each successive generation of thoughtful
and cultivated men, as examples of truth and of demonstration ; and
have thus become standard points of reference, among cultivated men,
whenever they speak of truth, knowledge, or proof. Thus Mathe-
matics has not only a disciplinal but an historical interest. This is
peculiarly the case with those portions of Mathematics which we have
mentioned. We find geometrical proof adduced in illustration of the
VI PREFACE.
nature of reasoning, in the earliest speculations on this subject, the
Dialogues of Plato ; we find geometrical proof one of the main sub-
jects of discussion in some of the most recent of such speculations, as
those of Dugald Stewart and his contemporaries. The recollection
of the truths of Elementary Geometry has, in all ages, given a meaning
and a reality to the best attempts to explain man's power of arriving
at truth. Other branches of Mathematics have, in like manner,
become recognized examples, among educated men, of man's powers
of attaining truth."
Dr. Pemberton, in the preface to his view of Sir Isaac Newton's
Discoveries, makes mention of the circumstance, " that Newton used
to speak with regret of his mistake, at the beginning of his Mathe-
matical Studies, in having applied himself to the works of Descartes
and other Algebraical writers, before he had considered the Elements
of Euclid with the attention they deserve."
To these we may subjoin the opinion of Mr. John Stuart Mill,
which he has recorded in his invaluable System of Logic, (Vol. li.
p. 180) in the following terms. " The value of Mathematical instruc-
tion as a preparation for those more difficult investigations (physiology,
society, government, &c.) consists in the applicability not of its doc-
trines, but of its method. Mathematics will ever remain the most
perfect type of the Deductive Method in general ; and the applications
of Mathematics to the simpler branches of physics, furnish the only
school in which philosophers can effectually learn the most difficult
and important portion of their art, the employment of the laws of
simpler phenomena for explaining and predicting those of the more
complex. These grounds are quite sufficient for deeming mathemati-
cal training an indispensable basis of real scientific education, and
regarding, with Plato, one who is dytutfiiTpnTo?, as wanting in one of
the most essential qualifications for the successful cultivation of the
higher branches of philosophy."
In addition to these authorities it may be remarked, that the new
Regulations which were confirmed by a Grace of the Senate on the
11th of May, 1846, assign to Geometry and to Geometrical methods,
a more important place in the Examinations both for Honors and
for the Ordinary Degree in this University.
Trinity College, RP.
3farch 1, 1850.
This Edition (the fifth), has been augmented by upwards of forty
pages of additional Notes, Questions and Geometrical Exercises.
Trinity College, R. P.
November 5, 1859.
CONTENTS.
Preface to the Third Edition , c iii
First Book of the Elements 1
Notes to the First Book 42
Questions on the First Book 59
On the Ancient Geometrical Analysis 64
Geometrical Exercises on Book I ,..,„« 69
Second Book of the Elements 85
Notes to the Second Book 99
Note on the Algebraical Symbols & Abbreviations used in Geometry 1 09
Questions on the Second Book 110
Geometrical Exercises on Book II 113
Third Book of the Elements 120
Notes to the Third Book 153
Questions on the Third Book 157
Geometrical Exercises on Book III 160
Fourth Book of the Elements 175
Notes to the Fourth Book 190
Questions on the Fourth Book 193
Geometrical Exercises on Book IV 196
Fifth Book of the Elements 204
Notes to the Fifth Book 235
Questions on the Fifth Book 257
Sixth Book of the Elements â– 259
Notes to the Sixth Book 294
Questions on the Sixth Book 299
Geometrical Exercises on Book VI 302
Solutions, Hints, &c. on Book I 313
II 323
Ill 326
IV . 338
VI 345
Index to the Geometrical Exercises 356
â–
LIBER CANTABRIGIENSIS.
PAET. I.
_^^ Account of the Aids afforded to poor Students^
the encouragements offered to diligent Students, and
the rewards conferred on successful Students, in the Uni-
versity of Cambridge ; to which is prefixed a Collection
of Ma/rims, Aphorisms, ^c. Designed for the Use of
Learners. By Egbert Potts, M.A., Trinity College.
Fcap. Svo.,pp. 570^ price 5s. 6d.
" It was not a bad idea to prefix to the many encouragements alForded to students
in the University of Cambridge, a selection of maxims drawn from the writings ot
men who have sliown that learning is to be judged by its fruits in social and
individual life."— 2'fte Literary Churchman.
" A work like this was much -wanted.."— ClericalJoumal.
*' The book altogether is one of merit and xalne."— Guardian.
" The several parts of this book are most interesting and mstT\ictiye."—i:ducational
Times.
" No doubt many will thank Mr. Potts for the very valuable information he has
afforded in this laborious compilation.'' — Critic.
" A vast amount of information is compressed into a small compass, at the cost
evidently of great labour and pains. The Aphorisms which form a prefix of 174
pages, may suggest useful reflections to earnest students."— jTAe Patriot.
John W. Parker, Son, & Bourn, West Strand, London.
PAET II.
Containing an Account (I) of the recent changes in the
Statutes made under the powers of the Act (19 and 20 Vict,
cap. 88).* (2) Of the Minor Scholarships instituted and
open to the competition of Students hefore Residence: (3)
Of the Course of Collegiate and University Studies at
Cambridge. Price 2s. 6d.
EUCLID'S
ELEMENTS OF GEOMETRY.
BOOK L
DEFINITIONS.
A POINT is that which has no parts, or which has no magnitude.
II.
A line is length without breadth.
III.
The extremities of a line are points.
IV.
A straight line is that which lies evenly between its extreme points.
V.
A superficies is that which has only length and breadth.
VI.
The extremities of a superficies are lines.
VII.
A plane superficies is that in which any two points being taken, the
straight line between them lies wholly in that superficies.
VIII.
A plane angle is the inclination of two lines to each other in a
plane, which meet together, but are not in the same direction.
IX.
A plane rectilineal angle is the inclination of two straight lines to
one another, which meet together, but are not in the same straight line.
I2Z
s
Euclid's elements.
N.B. If there be only one angle at a point, it may be expressed by
a letter placed at that point, as the angle at E : but when several angles
are at one point B, either of them is expressed by three letters, of which
the letter that is at the vertex of the angle, that is, at the point in which
the straight lines that contain the angle meet one another, is put between
the other two letters, and one of these two is somewhere upon one of
these straight lines, and the other upon the other line. Thus the angle
which is contained by the straight lines AB, CB, is named the angle
ABCy or CBA ; that which is contained by AB, DB, is named the angle
ABD, or DBA ; and that which is contained by DB^ CB^ is called the
angle DBC, or CBD.
X.
When a straight line standing on another straight line, makes the
adjacent angles equal to one another, each of these angles is called a
right angle ; and the straight line which stands on the other is called
a perpendicular to it.
XL
An obtuse angle is that which is greater than a right angle.
XII.
An acute angle is that which is less than a right angle.
XIII.
A term or boundary is the extremity of any thing.
XIV.
A figure is that which Is enclosed by one or more boundaries.
I
DEFINITIONS.
XV.
A circle is a plane figure contained by one line, which is called the
circumference, and is such that all straight lines drawn from a certain
point within the figure to the circumference, are equal to one another.
XVI.
And this point is called the center of the circle.
XVII.
A diameter of a circle is a straight line drawn through the center,
and terminated both ways by the circumference.
XVIII.
A semicircle is the figure contained by a diameter and the part of
the circumference cut off by the diameter.
XIX.
The center of a semicircle is the same with that of the circle.
XX.
Eectilineal figures are those which are contained by straight lines.
XXI.
Trilateral figures, or triangles, by three straight lines.
XXII.
Jl^uadrilateral, by four straight lines.
XXIII.
Multilateral figures, or polygons, by more than four straight lines.
b2
EUCLID S ELEMENTS.
XXIV.
Of three-sided figures, an equilateral triangle is that which has
three equal sides.
XXV.
An isosceles triangle is that which has two sides equo I.
XXVI.
A scalene triangle is that which has three unequal sides.
XXVII.
A right-angled triangle is that which has a right angle.
.^L.
XXVIII.
An obtuse-angled triangle is that which has an obtuse angle.
XXIX.
An acute-angled triangle is that which has three acute angles.
\
z.
XXX.
_\
Of quadrilateral or four-sided figures, a square has all its sides equal
and all its angles right angles.
DEFINITIONS.
XXXI.
An oblong is that which has all its angles right angles, but has not
all its sides equal.
XXXII.
A rhombus has all its sides equal, but its angles are not right angles.
XXXIII.
A rhomboid has its opposite sides equal to each other, but all its
sides are not equal, nor its angles right angles.
XXXIV.
All other four-sided figures besides these, are called Trapeziums.
XXXV.
Parallel straight lines are such as are in the same plane, and which
being produced ever so far both ways, do not meet.
A.
A parallelogram is a four-sided figure, of which the opposite sides
are parallel: and the diameter, or the diagonal is the straight line
joining two of its opposite angles.
POSTULATES.
I.
Let it be granted that a straight line may be drawn from any one
point to any other point.
II.
That a terminated straight line may be produced to any length in
a straight line.
III.
And that a circle may be described from any center, at any distance
from that center.
3 Euclid's elements.
AXIOMS.
I.
Things which are equal to the same thing are equal to one another.
II.
If eqiials be added to equals, the wholes are equal.
III.
If equals be taken from equals, the remainders are equal.
IV.
If equals be added to unequals, the wholes are unequal.
V.
If equals be taken from unequals, the remainders are unequal.
VI.
Things which are double of the same, are equal to one another.
VII.
Things which are halves of the same, are equal to one another.
VIII.
Magnitudes which coincide with one another, that is, which exact! \
fill the same space, are equal to one another.
IX.
The whole is greater than its part.
X.
Two straight lines cannot enclose a space.
XI.
All right angles are equal to one another.
XII.
If a straight line meets two straight lines, so as to make the two
interior angles on the same side of it taken together less than two
right angles ; these straight lines being continually produced, shall at
length meet upon that side on which are the angles which are less than
iwo right angles.
BOOK I. PROP. I, U.
PROPOSITION I. PROBLEM.
To describe an equilateral triangle upon a given finite straight line.
Let ABhe the given straight line.
It is required to describe an equilateral triangle upon AJB,
c
From the center A, at the distance AD, describe the circle BCD-,
(post. 3.)
from the center B, at the distance BA, describe the circle A CE ;
and from C, one of the points in which the circles cut one another,
draw the straight lines CA, CB to the points A^ B. (post. 1.)
Then ^^C shall be an equilateral triangle.
Because the point A is the center of the circle BCD,
therefore ^Cis equal to AB ', (def. 15.)
and because the point B is the center of the circle A CE,
therefore BC is equal to AB ;
but it has been proved that ^ C is equal to AB ;
therefore A C, BC are each of them equal to AB ;
but things which are equal to the same thing are equal to one another ;
therefore ACis equal to BC; (ax. 1.)
wherefore AB, BC, CA are equal to one another:
and the triangle ABC is therefore equilateral,
and it is described upon the given straight line AB.
Which was requii*ed to be done.
PROPOSITION II. PROBLEM.
From a given point, to draw a straight line equal to a given straight line.
Let A be the given point, and B C the given straight line.
It is required to di'aw from the point A, a straight line equal to BC.
From the point A to B draw the straight line AB; (post. 1.)
upon AB describe the equilateral triangle ABD, (i. 1.)
and produce the straight lines DA, DB to E and F; (post. 2.)
from the center B, at the distance BC, describe the circle CGH,
(post. 3.) cutting DF in the point G:
and from the center D, at the distance DG, describe the circle GKL,
cutting AE in the point L.
Then the straight line AL shall be equal to BC.
Because the point B is the center of the circle CGII,
therefore BCh equal to BG-, (def. 15.)
and because D is the center of the circle GKL,
therefore DL is equal to DG,
and BA, DB parts of them are equal ; (l. 1.)
therefore the remainder AL is equal to the remainder BG; (ax. 3.)
but it has been shewn that BC is equal to BG,
wherefore AL and ^Care each of them equal to BG;
and things that are equal to the same thing are equal to one another ;
therefore the straight line AL is equal to BC. (ax. 1.)
Wherefore from the given point A, a straight line AL has been drawn
equal to the given straight line BC. Which was to be done.
PROPOSITION III. PROBLEM.
From the greater of two given straight lines to cut off a part equal to the less.
Let AB and Cbe the two given straight lines, of which A.B is the
greater.
It is required to cut off from^ J? the greater, a part equal to C, the less.
D
From the point A draw the straight line AD equal to C; (l. 2.)
and from the center A, at the distance AD, describe the circle DEF
(post. 3.) cutting AB in the point E.
Then AE shall be equal to C.
Because A is the center of the circle DEF,
therefore AE is equal to AD-, (def. 15.)
but the straight line C is equal to AD; (constr.)
whence AE and C are each of them equal to AD;
wherefore the straight line AE is equal to C. (ax. 1.)
And therefore from AB the greater of two straight lines, a part AE
has been cut off equal to C, the less. Which was to be done.
PROPOSITION IV. THEOREM.
If two triangles have tico sides of the one equal to two sides of the other,
each to each, and have likewise the angles contained by those sides equal to
each other ; they shall likewise have their bases or third sides equal, and
the two triangles shall he eqiial, and their other angles shall be equal, each
to each, viz. those to which the equal sides are opposite.
Let ABC, DEF be two triangles, which have the two sides AB,
A C equal to the two sides DE, DF, each to each, viz. AB to DE, and
^ C to DF, and the included angle BA C equal to the included angle
EDF.
BOOK I. PROP, jy, V. 9
Then shall the base ^Cbe equal to the base JEF; and the triangle
ABC to the triangle DEF-, and the other angles to which the equal
sides are opposite shall be equal, each to each, viz. the angle ABC to
the angle JDFF, and the angle A CB to the angle DFF. ^
I ..„,._.„.„..
^^ that the point A may be on J), and the straight line AB on DB\
then the point B shall coincide with the point E^
because AB is equal to EE;
and AB coinciding with EE,
the straight line A C shall fall on EF^
because the angle BA C is equal to the angle EEF\ -^
therefore also the point C shall coincide with the point jP,
because AC\% equal to EF\
but the point B was shewn to coincide with the point E ;
wherefore the base ^C shall coincide with the base EF;
because the point B coinciding with E, and C with F,